LA
CONSTRUCCIÓN CIENTÍFICA DEL SEXO
THE
SCIENTIFIC CONSTRUCTION OF SEX
Leah Daniela Muñoz Contreras[1]
Resumen
Este
texto presenta un análisis sobre la emergencia y la construcción científica del
sexo a partir de un análisis historiográfico que comprende el periodo de
finales del siglo xviii al siglo xx. En el análisis se muestra que el
desarrollo de este saber científico ha operado a partir de una triple
coproducción de (i) taxonomías y nomenclaturas, (ii) etiologías y (iii)
regímenes de subjetividad. De igual forma se propone que en esta historia de la
ciencia surgió en pleno siglo xx
un tercer modelo sobre el sexo, siguiendo la historización propuesta por Thomas
Laqueur, que resultó fundamental no solamente para posibilitar la existencia material
de nuevas identidades sexuales sino también para entender el contexto social y
político de la época en el escenario occidental. El presente texto contribuye a
complejizar y entender de mejor forma la relación entre ciencia, sexo-género y
subjetividad de tal manera que la historia de la ciencia permita abrir un
diálogo con las problemáticas de nuestros días.
Palabras
Clave: sexo,
ciencia y género, historia de la ciencia, historia de la subjetividad, sexualidades
Abstract
This paper presents an analysis of the emergence of
sex as an object of study and its scientific construction, based on a
historiographic analysis which covers the period from the end of the 18th
century to the 20th
century. The study shows that the scientific development of
this knowledge has operated through a threefold production of (i) taxonomies
and nomenclatures, (ii) etiologies and (iii) regimes of subjectivity. I propose
further that in the history of this area of science, a third model of sex
emerged in the twentieth century to add to the previous two, following the
historicizing promoted by Thomas Laqueur, which was fundamental not only for making
the material existence of new sexual identities a possibility, but also for understanding the social and
political context of the time, in the western world. The
present article helps to explain the complexities of the relation of science to
sex/gender and subjectivity, so it can be understood better, and shows how a historical
account of the science on this topic can to contribute to starting a dialogue
on problems of the present.
Keywords:
sex, science and gender,
history of science, history of subjectivity, sexualities
recepción: 6 de septiembre de 2019/aceptación: 17 de
enero de 2020
The main objective of this article is to produce a
historiography of the emergence and construction of sex as an object of
scientific study. The aim is to show how scientific knowledge of an aspect of
sexuality has developed through the threefold production of (i) taxonomies and nomenclatures, and
(ii) etiologies, which in turn contribute to the constitution of (iii) a regime
of subjectivities concerned with scientific knowledge of sexuality.
Taxonomies and nomenclatures are
understood in this article as the classifications, and the terms, used by
scientists to explain sexual and gender diversity by considering it in terms of
groups or classes of individuals thought to have certain characteristics in
common. By etiologies is meant the causal explanations given by scientists for
a phenomenon, in this case that of sexual and gender diversity. And the term regime of subjectivity, inspired by the
work of Michel Foucault in La Historia de
la Sexualidad Vol. I (2011) and in La
Hermenéutica del Sujeto (2002), refers to a model where the subject is
judged and ruled, or judges and rules himself, by his or her belonging to a
class.
The notion of a threefold coproduction,
also inspired by Foucault, aims to capture the process whereby science, as it
explains the various sexual behaviors that exist, creates sexual
classifications that are, in their turn, explained by the postulation of
etiologies, or causal mechanisms, which then create classes of subjects. At the
same time, these classifications and etiologies create regimes of subjectivity,
in so far as they serve as a hermeneutics for the subject, that is, as a form
through which the subject can be explained but can also comprehend himself.
Here it is important to note that
the way in which the notion of a regime of subjectivity is used does not only
refer to the forms that explain subjects but also to the therapeutics and
material interventions applied by science and medicine, which many subjects
decide to apply to themselves, as members of a particular classification or
class of subject.
In other words, the idea of a threefold
coproduction can show that at least in this case of sexuality, as it explains
sexual behaviors, science creates forms of subjectivity or classes of subject. But
the threefold coproduction also explains how science incorporates into its
taxonomies and etiologies, other taxonomies, regimes of subjectivity and
narratives that had been produced by examples of sexual diversity in contexts
that were not scientific or medical, which leaves the explanation of subjects open,
and not historically determined by scientific authority, but free to respond to
the historical development of science itself and of the sexual collectivities
involved.
The importance of thinking about the
scientific construction of sex using the methodology of a threefold coproduction
lies in the fact that this provides us with a complex image of the dynamics of science
in the construction of sex as an object of scientific study. The complexity of
the image is due to the recognition that scientific explanations produce
subjectivities, and that subjectivities in turn are liable to affect the
explanations given by science.
The
second objective of the article is to show how, in the course of this history,
another model of sex emerged after the historicizing of sex developed by Laqueur
(1994), which would become essential for explaining the political and social changes
of the twentieth century, when sexual diversities and women acquired greater
social visibility on the political scene in the Western context.
This
work has both academic and political motivations. The former is the wish to
develop a historiographic and philosophical study of sex in the framework of
the larger theoretical task of showing how a field of studies of sexuality,
rooted in a scientific approach, arose, and trying to explain how objects of
scientific study are created.
A
historiographic analysis of this kind, shows how the scientific construction of
sex took place, and how, in the course of this construction, a series of
reductionist, biologic and essentialist explanations were adopted that created
a “truth about sex”, which produced both
new sexual identities and new ways of expressing one’s sexuality; a necessary
step in the development of a critique of the contemporary biologic conceptions
still being produced by science today.
But
our historiography of the scientific construction of sex is also an attempt to
show the complexities of the relations between science, sex/gender, and
subjectivity, as we hope to show that in science, the notion of sex has never
been self-evident, rather that its construction has been the result of
controversies between different scientific disciplines, influenced by social
contexts.
From
this comes the political motivation of the study, as today in different parts
of the world we are passing through a political context in which there are anti-rights
groups who believe that appealing to a constructivist notion of sex is to be
ideological, hence to have a “gender ideology” opposed to what science has to
say, while at the same time they ignore the complicated history of sex and what
the history of science can teach us on the subject.
Thus
the text is divided into four sections. The first presents the account given by
Thomas Laqueur and shows how his work explains the first two main models of sex,
and the historical reasons for the replacement of one by the other. In this
section we shall also show how the three parts of the coproduction of each of
the two models are thought to be linked.
The
second and third sections will contain the proposal of a third model for sex,
and both the scientific and the political reasons for its emergence will be
explored. Every paragraph will show how the three elements of the coproduction of
each of these models of sex are linked. The final part will present the
Conclusions.
The
historicizing of sex
One of the
principal contributions of Thomas Laqueur (1994) in his classic work The Construction of Sex, is to have shown
the historical character of concepts of sex. He proposes that there are two
models of sex which have been used to explain sexual differences, and gives
historical reasons for why one model replaced the other.
The
first model is the one-sex model. This had its origin in the writings of the
Greek physician Galen of Pergamon, and up until the eighteenth and nineteenth
centuries it had been the predominant model for explaining differences between
the sexes. According to this idea, men and women had the same
sexual organs but in one case they were inside the body and in the other they
were outside, making the differences between men and women differences of
degree and not of type. These differences showed women to be imperfect or
defective versions of men, which makes the model hierarchical. The physiology
of the model accepted the theory of universal fluids or humors that the heat of
the body would give a particular form to, and this explained the differences
between men and women (Laqueur, 1994).
In
this model, as explained by Vázquez-García (2018, p. 19), the nature of the body
was fluid and open-ended and might be influenced by activities and occupations,
which is explained by the fact that in this model the relation of the body to the
environment was more permeable than today.
In short, sex here was a “rank” that was expressed both in a person’s
physical condition and in his social attributes, both in his dress, and his
genitalia.
At
the end of the Enlightenment, after the eighteenth century, as Laqueur (1994)
tells us, this model was replaced by that of two sexes. The new model continued
to be hierarchical in the sense that a natural or biological inferiority was
attributed to the woman, but now the difference between the sexes was one of
type and no longer one of degree as it had been in the first model. In effect, there
was thought to be a radical difference between men and women that created two
opposite and completely different sexes, which were complementary and incommensurable
in all aspects both of the body and of the personality. This model was
functional, as the differences between the sexes were to be found in their
functions, especially those of sex and reproduction, which were termed
“generative functions”.
According
to Laqueur (1994), this change of conceptions about the sexes was due to
political factors, as the two-sex model sought to maintain and naturalize the
social hierarchy of men and women, inherited from the old stratified order, and
so put an end to the liberal revolutions fomented by Enlightenment ideas that
presented both men and women as equal citizens. Thus the two-sex model came to
legitimize the dominant ideas of the time such as the roles given to women,
focused on reproduction and the “private sphere”.
Sociologist Myra Hird (2004, p. 22) also
maintains that this transition from one model to another was not the result of
any discovery made by medicine, but of political changes. But in addition to
political factors she notes changes in epistemology that gave the same body,
new meanings. On the basis of scientific knowledge, the Enlightenment brought in
a way of approaching the body that meant breaking it up into its parts in order
for it to reveal its truth. So what sex, and sexual difference, was
essentially, was determined by visible objects.
It was in this context that the
two-sex model was constructed by invoking biological differences, but for this
to occur biology had to be established as a science and, as explained by Vázquez-García
(2018, p. 20), life now had to be regarded as a desacralized space, a process
left to itself and ruled by its own rules and regulations. From this moment on
we can say correctly that biologic projects on sex started, looking at bones,
gonads, hormones, chromosomes and genes to find the essence of what might be
the natural cause regulating the differences between the sexes.
So far, we can see that in each of
the two models, the relation between taxonomy and etiology, and the subjectivity
regime, is judged differently. In the first model there is a taxonomy that has,
as well as men and women, intermediate conditions such as “various types of
hermaphrodite, men who produce milk or menstruate, women with a prominent
clitoris or viragos, tongue-and-groove men, etc.” (Vázquez-García, 2018, p.
16).
Here the etiology of each sex is
given by a physiology of humors where the body is open to the environment. Those
in the intermediate categories could show improvements to their sex as a
function of changes in the balance of the humors, and women who adopted male
customs and clothes could present physical changes that turned them into men (Vázquez-García,
2018, p. 16-17).
It is important to note that as
there were no dichotomies before the nineteenth century of nature vs. society,
or biology vs. culture, the sexes were explained by appealing to Nature, not in
the biological sense it has now, but understanding it as a moral order that
expressed the will of God. This vision of the world was backed by Galenic
medicine. This needs to be said because in this etiology the existence of
“hermaphrodites” was considered a natural possibility, something rare but not
monstrous (Vázquez-García, 2018, p.16).
With regard to the regimes of
subjectivity in this single-sex model, sex was conceived of as a degree or
rank, which justified the division of the sexes that was actually maintained by
the Church and civil authorities. In the two-sex model, now rooted in the
nineteenth century idea of biology, the only taxonomy allowed was one in which
men and women existed under the premise of radical difference. The possibility
of intermediate states was denied and everything that did not fit into the
binary man-woman construct could only be found in the taxonomies of late
nineteenth century sexologists.
One example is given by the German
psychiatrist Richard von Krafft-Ebing, who placed into the field of the scornfully
labeled “sexual inverts”, a great variety of practices and sexual behaviors that
were mainly associated with homosexuality, but also included subjects who identified
with the opposite sex (Meyerowitz, 2004).
The etiology at play in this model
was no longer that of a body open to the environment, as in the single-sex
model, but a closed-off body where causality was to be found in the gonads and their
secretions. The era of the gonads had come to mean that the essence of sex,
gender and sexuality was to be found in these (Meyerowitz, 2004, p. 27). That
is why, in the case of “hermaphrodites”, the truth of sex was sought mainly by appealing
to the gonads. In the case of “sexual inverts”, an etiology of pathology was
applied in which doctors and psychiatrists considered their condition as an
illness or a perversion and its cause was supposed to lie in the gonads.
In respect of the regimes of
subjectivity, these etiologies made subjects to be seen, and to see themselves,
as ill. In the case of homosexuality, practices were followed in which the
gonads of heterosexual men were transplanted to homosexual men as part of a
therapy seeking to restore heterosexuality (Meyerowitz, 2004, p. 17). With
regard to “hermaphrodites”, these became doubtful cases that had to be put
under the magnifying glass of specialists and forensic doctors so they could
“diagnose” the real sex, and if they found a contradiction between the “real
sex” and the subject’s identity, then the identity had to be corrected under
the mandate of biology.
The
third model of sex
So far we have
presented the two models of sex that came out of the work of Thomas Laqueur,
and have shown how in these two models, the taxonomies, etiologies and regimes
of subjectivity involved in a threefold production of the model, were all
linked. These models are the ones most used in studies of science and studies
of the body as they allow the historicity of narratives of the body and the
ontology of sex to be taken into account. In this section our aim is to show
how a third model of sex emerged in the first half of the twentieth century, in
the wake of the difficulties that the second model came up against.
This
third model was one of two sexes, hierarchical, not functionalist and not
radically exclusive; and now bodies are thought of as being on a gradient. The
differences between the sexes are noted, but so are the similarities between
them, so this model is not committed to a metaphysics in which anatomy and
physiology are incommensurable. It is on the basis of this model, that sex
comes to be thought of as something that can be modified and altered by
medicine.
The
new model of sex arose as a result of the crisis that the second model faced
both for political reasons and for the reasons given by scientific practice at
the start of the twentieth century. The former derived from the fact that as
women had begun to occupy posts of paid employment and started to obtain higher
education, and a women’s movement was formed to demand equal rights with men,
it became clear that men and women did not naturally belong to “different
spheres” as the model of radical exclusion between the sexes held (Preciado,
2010). Also, the prominence acquired by male and female homosexual collectives
made it plain that there was not a radical dividing line between the sexes in
the world of sexual desire, but, on the contrary, desire for men and desire for
women, as for masculinity and femininity, existed in both groups (Meyerowitz,
2004, p. 22).
This
was not only a political but also a scientific fact, as researchers had found
that with respect to evidence, the idea of the sexes as incommensurable was
unsustainable. For scientific reasons, it was necessary to have a new
conception of sex, and evidence that came principally from the recently created
study of endocrinology allowed the third model of sex to take shape.
This
new conception of sex was based on, and developed from, the theory of
bisexuality, as it was called. The theory of bisexuality, developed from the
early years of the twentieth century onwards, held that the sexes were
biologically, that is, organically, bisexual, as they both had some aspects in
common, not just in terms of masculinity and femininity but also in terms of
biological sex.
Meyerowitz
(2004, p. 23) reports that the theory of bisexuality began to receive the
backing of studies in embryology, that showed there was a sexual
differentiation common to the two sexes in the process of development, and that
of statistical studies on psychic and corporeal differences, which showed that
the sexes were not two clearly distinct groups but that there was an overlap
between them.
Thus
the theory of bisexuality sustained a conception of sex as an abstract continuum,
and the sex of every individual was really a matter of degree, where the male
and female sexes are substances with different proportions. Both
Hirschfeld and Havelock Ellis stuck to this idea and became disseminators of
the bisexuality theory (Meyerowitz, 2004, p. 26).
Discoveries in endocrinology in the
1930s were fundamental to the formation of what is called the third model, as
the discovery that there were male and female hormones in both sexes gave empirical
support to the idea that there were male and female elements in both sexes,
only in different proportions. In this way the conception of sex as an individual variation at a
point on a spectrum came to replace the second model, of mutual exclusion.
This
new third model of sex would reorganize the threefold relation between the
taxonomies, etiologies and regimes of subjectivity involved, in a different
way. With regard to taxonomies, we find that Magnus Hirschfeld, one of the
principal defenders of this conception of sex, was interested in
depathologizing the subject, by recognizing the existence of “sexual
intermediaries” (“hermaphrodites”, androgynes, homosexuals and transvestites),
as part of human variety (Meyerowitz, 2004).
There
is a fundamental difference here with the taxonomies related to the second
model of sex, as all of these placed on the side of perversion and pathology
all sexual subjects that the model could not explain as part of a notion of
radical mutual exclusion by the two sexes. In fact, Meyerowitz (2004, p. 98) reports
that in the United States, this confrontation between conceptions of sex as
being either on a continuum or mutually exclusive, was expressed in the
theories of a group of doctors who adhered to the first position, and the group
of psychoanalysts, psychologists and psychiatrists who held to the second idea.
In
spite of which, it does not follow that the third model was free of
pathologizing connotations, as, although Hirschfeld was thinking from the point
of view of human variation, there were other doctors who had an interest in
remedying what was considered to be a “biological defect”. This connects
directly with etiologies,
because in this third model there were etiologies of human variation at play,
based on individual variations of sex understood as a continuum, just as much
as etiologies of biological failures. Whether these etiologies were of
variation or of biological failure they had within them a clearly biologic
element that anchored the essence of sex, of masculinity and femininity, no
longer in the gonads but in hormones.
The
regimes of subjectivity that stemmed from this were of two types. Firstly those
committed to depathologizing the topic did not seek to remedy something that
was considered to be a biological failing, and was the line taken by Hirschfeld
and by the Austrian philosopher Otto Weininger in the first decades of the
twentieth century. In fact, Hirschfeld was committed to promoting what he
considered sexual freedom and in the Institute for the Science of Sex he sought
to help “transvestites” who wanted a change of sex (Meyerowitz, 2004, p. 30).
Secondly,
commitments to depathologizing the topic were not shared by all the doctors as
there were still some who claimed that once the causes of non-hegemonic sexual
behaviors, understood as biological failures, were known, it was possible to
restore these subjects to cisheterosexuality[2].
Also,
although it conceived of sex as being on a continuum, this model still
legitimized an unequal society, as it stemmed from a hierarchical view of the
sexes in which the female was associated with inferior characteristics and the
male with superior characteristics. The notion of the body as being on a
gradient explained, for example, the social success of some women in terms of their
having a higher degree of masculinity (Meyerowitz,
2004, p. 25).
In
therapeutic terms, this third model of sex re-launched the possibility of
changing one’s sex with greater force, as the notion of the body on a gradient
and the identification of sexual hormones as sexual markers made it possible to
explain that changing sex was a natural possibility, allowed by the very
biology of the body, as seen in the proportions of hormones.
We
can therefore say that this third model of sex is reconceptualized and ceases
to be immutable, as distinct from the second model. The new model resulted in a
historical break-up of the conceptual and material understanding of sex, as it
was on the basis of this model that for the first time in human history, sex,
primarily governed by proportions of hormones, would be thought of as something
that could be intervened in and directed. As a result, throughout the twentieth
century, a whole series of medical technologies using hormones arose, and these
would make it possible not only for transsexual subjects to appear, but for there
to be more control and regulation of sex, as in the case of contraceptive pills
that alter the cycles of hormones, hormones used by sportspeople to promote the
growth of muscular mass, and hormone supplements for women past menopause.
It is important to note on this last
point that this model, that allowed intervention in sex and its direction,
opened up a market for the pharmaceutical industry. Oudshoorn (2000) mentions
that the emergence of an endocrinology of sex, as well as keeping doctors and
scientists at work, was an attraction for pharmaceutical companies.
In
his work The Birth of Sex Hormones, Oudshoorn
(2000) also points out that in the twentieth century there arose another model
of sex, motivated mainly by endocrinology, which had discovered that the sexual
hormones originated and functioned in both sexes, and this had the effect of
displacing the essence of masculinity and femininity from specific organs,
where the anatomists had placed it, to quantities of hormones.
According
to Oudshoorn, this model had the effect of reformulating sex in terms of chemical
substances as well as bodily structures. Introducing the concept of sexual
hormones, understood as chemical messengers that controlled masculinity and
femininity, meant a break from the conceptualization of sex as it had been in
the past, as it went from being an anatomical entity to being a chemical agency
(Oudshoorn, 2000, p. 110). Endocrinology would also mean a change in the study
of sex, now looking for its causes instead of trying to identify it, as well as
the introduction of a quantitative theory of sex and the body. Sex was no
longer an absolute, but became a relative specificity, and the difference
between the sexes was no longer one of type but of degree. Oudshoorn (2000) also
notes the capacity that this model has for accounting for the sexual diversity
of individuals, both in terms of physical characteristics and of personality,
by proposing a biological basis for sex.
Both
the model reported on by Oudshoorn and the model proposed in this article agree
that the sexes are now conceived of as being different in terms of degree and
not of type, so we are no longer dealing with a model of radical exclusion of
one sex by the other. Another point of agreement is our recognition that a
quantitative theory of the body and sex, is derived from this new model, where
differences are thought of in terms of quotients of hormones. Finally, we agree
that the new model has the capacity to provide a biological explanation that
integrates the various sexual subjectivities.
The
differences between the two new models are, that the model proposed here takes
note of the fact that the relation between the sexes was still being regarded
hierarchically, with the female sex considered inferior, but we have now come
to a non-functionalist notion of sex, which means that sex is no longer
centered on definitions based on the reproductive function of evolutionary
biologists, for whom to be male is to have the function of producing
spermatozoa and to be female is to have the function of producing ovaries (Guerrero-McManus,
2013). Instead, we have advanced to a notion of sex understood as a sexed body.
Another difference is that the model proposed here recovers the mutable and
interventionist character that sex and the body acquired in the first decades
of the twentieth century, and this allows access to a conceptual apparatus for
taking into account how sex is socially altered by the technological and conceptual
products of science.
Finally
Oudshoorn explains that the reasons for passing from the second to the third
model were to be found principally in the discoveries of endocrinology, while
the model I propose here not only takes up the discoveries of endocrinology but
also the role played by the social and political context in which women’s,
homosexual, and lesbian movements brought scientists to recognize that their
conception of sex did not coincide with the reality it claimed to describe.
In
the next section we shall see how this third model was modified in the middle
of the twentieth century when the category of gender came in, a modification that Oudshoorn did not consider in her
model.
The third model of sex with the arrival
of gender
In this final section it is proposed that half way
through the twentieth century the third model of sex underwent modifications as
a result of interdisciplinary conflicts in the United States, debating the
causes of gender identity among intersexual and transsexual persons.
What the third model that came out
of these discussions retained of the original third model is that it was still
one of two sexes, non-functionalist, and not of radical exclusion. The
differences between the earlier and the later versions of the third model are
that sex was now no longer considered as an absolute ontology for organizing
the bodily, psychological and social field, but as an ontology of biological
causes that gives an account of how a body develops as soma. Also, in this
model of a sexed body, as well as thinking of it as being on a gradient, it started
to be thought of as a stratified sexed body, that is to say, an ontogenetic
comprehension of the sexed body began to consolidate in which, with the sexual
development of the body, examples of sex were to be found at every one of the
levels of organization or bodily strata (chromosomes, tissues, organs, hormone
levels, etc.)[3].
The historical reasons for the
emergence of this new model are found, first, in the appearance in the works of
John Money, of the category of gender, and secondly, in the controversy between
doctors, psychoanalysts, and psychologists over the etiology and the
therapeutics of gender identity among intersexual and transsexual persons.
The research of John Money and the Hampson
brothers established in the mid nineteen fifties, through studies of the
morphology, physiology and psychosexual development of intersexual children, that
masculinity and femininity did not have their causes in biology (Fausto-Sterling,
2006, p. 66). As a result of this, Money defined the category of gender as a
behavior and an attitude that had its cause in environmental factors understood
principally as nurture (Fausto-Sterling, 2006, p. 66).
With
the invention of the category gender,
a division was forged in the order of things that signaled a biological origin
on the one hand, and on the other, social conditioning appropriate for the
sexual behaviors of men and women, that is, it grouped as sex a set of biological characteristics that differed for each
group and would result in a sexual dimorphism, and as gender, the different sexual behaviors, male and female, of men and
women, which would have a social origin.
This is how the conception of sex
that came with the previous third model was restricted to being only a set of
biological characteristics without reaching as far as the behaviors of
subjects. The works published by Money, in turn, were a confirmation from
another field of science, in anthropological studies produced since the 1920s,
that there were variations in “gender roles” across cultures, whose cause was
to be found in social learning.
This model, called
“environmentalist” was the approach defended by Money in the controversy over
the causes of gender identity, in which doctors defended a biologic focus while
psychoanalysts held to an approach based on the psychodynamics of infancy. It was
due to this controversy about the etiology of gender identity that doctors no
less than psychologists and psychiatrists found it necessary to define what sex
was, in order to be able to be able to describe the kind of relation that sex
had with gender identity, and then if some component of sex was the most
essential and determining, reveal the truth about sex and the subject.
Money proposed a model for sex,
stratified in six levels, which was made up of: chromosome sex, foetal gonad
sex, foetal hormone sex, internal reproductive sex, cerebral sex and genital
sex (Fausto-Sterling, 2012, p. 10). For Harry Benjamin, sex had six components,
which were: chromosome sex, genetic sex, gonad sex, germinal sex, hormone,
anatomical, psychological, legal and social sex. From the work he had done with
transsexual subjects he deduced that on some levels sex could be modified
either by hormonal or surgical technologies (Meyerowitz, 2004, p. 118).
According to Meyerowitz (2004),
Stoller adopted a similar approach, because sex for him was not only a question
of chromosomes but consisted of various levels: chromosomes, interior genitals,
gonads, external genitals, hormonal states and secondary sexual characteristics.
What we can see from this is that
once sex was defined as a set of characteristics made up of different levels,
the body ceased to be thought of principally as a gradient because it was no
longer centered on hormonal determinism. So the body came to be thought of as a
composition of strata whose interactions gave a structure to the sex of the
individual. This idea was not against thinking of sex as a continuum, as the
new model did not reject the idea that sex had different ways of assuming form
that could not be limited to two mutually exclusive connections.
The taxonomies arising from this
model would include and give possibilities to transsexual, cissexual,
transgender and cisgender persons, transvestites, intersexuals, endosexuals and
the whole diversity of behaviors that get their meaning from the dichotomy of
sex and gender. The etiologies linked to this are many and varied, with on one
side those who adopt a biologic perspective on this model and appeal to
diversity or “biological failure” to explain gender as a causal extension of
sex, with the majority of approaches in biology and biomedicine being of this
type (Saraswast, Weinand and Safer, 2015).
A second type of etiology arising
from this model comes from the “environmentalist” or social approaches that
seek to explain the body as a biological cause, on the one hand, and as a
social cause, on the other. In this type of etiology are to be found the
approaches of psychology, sociology and feminist studies. In fact it is
important to point out that elaborations made in the tradition of feminist
studies have openly defended this model, or have assumed it, at least in its
most traditional version, where sex is soma and gender is culture.
With regard to the regimes of
subjectivity, this model would accept both the approach of human variation and
that of biological failure, but having admitted the distinction between sex and
gender this model is also open to, and has opened up, subjective paths to formulating
a social critique in relation to sexuality and gender. One example of which is
that of the women’s political movements, motivated by feminist theorizing on
the existence of a sex-gender system (Rubin, 1986) that imposes gender and
sexuality, which ran through the second half of the twentieth century in opposition
to the patriarchy. The trans, gay and lesbian movements of the second half of
the twentieth century and the start of the twenty-first were also influenced by
this model of sex.
In respect of the emergence of
identities, the transgender identity, as an identity critical of the insistence
made by medicine that surgery was required to reassign sex if transsexual
subjects were to be validated, arose in the nineteen eighties (Pons and Garosi,
2016), and differed from the transsexual identity on the basis of our model in
that the distinction between sex and gender made it possible to recognize that
gender could be changed without the need to alter sex technologically.
Another of the subjectivizing
effects that this model of sex has had may be seen in the reach and the impact
of the term gender all over the world not only in so far as it applies to
political movements but also in respect of its presence in public policies and
on political agendas.
Conclusions
In the course of
this article, following a historiographical strategy adopting the idea of a
threefold co-production, our aim has been to show the complexities of the
emergence historically of sex as an object of scientific study, which it was to
become as the result of debates over the years between different disciplines on
the classification, genesis and therapeutics of sex and sexual behaviors.
In this
historical account our commitment has been to a constructivism of sex that
allows us to see its historicity and the narratives of the body, and at the same
time see the social implications of this historicity and these narratives. This
transition from one model of the body to others shows us that, as explained by Guerrero-McManus
and Muñoz (2018), there is a historical ontology of the sexed body that defines
itself through controversies, and constantly changes.
Our
objective has been to show that the story of sex told to us by Laqueur is
really more complicated and that there are not two models of the body but
three, with each model redefining the body not just to take into account
scientific evidence but also to uphold a social order that it is intended to
legitimize.
Furthermore,
these re-conceptualizations of sex will bring in their wake different ways for
subjects to become subjects and be intervened in, which means the historicity
of sex is linked to the historicity of subjectivities. In this way, the
historical ontology of sex shows us the historicity of the different forms of
understanding the body, of living it and transforming it, and how the political
history of the subjects whom it is hoped to explain is involved in each
conception.
Finally,
to conclude this article, it is relevant to note that the feminist philosopher Alison Stone (2007) has developed an approach
to sex on the basis of GHP (groups of homeostatic properties), that shares the same
characteristics of thinking of the sexed body in terms of degrees, paying
attention to its various layers, and thinking of an ontology of biological
causes that would explain the body as soma.
In Stone’s
proposal, developed on the basis of studies of the philosophy of biology,
belonging to the male or the female group is decided by having a large enough
set of the relevant characteristics of either group. Here sex is also thought
of in terms of degrees (not proportions of hormones but considering the layers
that emerge from the ontogeny of the sexed body) on a continuum, as it is not necessary
to have all the relevant properties to belong to a particular sex but a large
enough set of them, so the sex they are given is not the same for all
individuals in a group as they have it in different degrees. This then
highlights, as the third model proposed in this article showed, that sex can no
longer be thought of as the consequence of an absolute property, but as a
relative attribute particular to each individual, who is the result of an
arrangement of a multiplicity of different properties.
Acknowledgements:
To DGAPA and the
project PAPIIT IN400318 “Ecología Queer y
Filosofía Ambiental. Articulaciones Conceptuales entre Naturaleza y Naturaleza
Humana” for the grant awarded for me
to complete my studies for a first degree in Biology, which has led to the
production of this article.
My thanks to Dra. Siobhan
Guerrero McManus, researcher at the Centro
de Investigaciones Interdisciplinarias en Ciencias y Humanidades-UNAM,
professor and friend, for her ideas and comments, which have enriched and
strengthened this paper.
Bibliography
Fausto-Sterling, A.
(2006). Cuerpos sexuados. La política de
género y la construcción de la sexualidad. Barcelona:
Melusina.
Fausto-Sterling, A. (2012). Sex/Gender. Biology in a Social World. New York: Taylor & Francis.
Foucault, M. (2002). La
hermenéutica del sujeto. México: Fondo de Cultura Económica.
Foucault, M.
(2011). Historia de la Sexualidad. Vol.
1. La Voluntad de Saber. México: Siglo XXI.
Guerrero-McManus, S.
(2013). ¿Naces o te haces? La ciencia
detrás de la homosexualidad. México: Paidós.
Guerrero-McManus, S. and Muñoz, L. (2018). Ontopolíticas del cuerpo trans: Controversia,
Historia e Identidad. In L. Raphael and A. Gómez (Eds.), Diálogos diversos para más mundos posibles. (pp. 71-94).
México: IIJ-UNAM.
Hird, M. (2004). Sex, Gender and Science. New York:
Palgrave.
Laqueur, T. (1994). La
construcción del sexo. Cuerpo y género desde los griegos hasta Freud. Madrid:
Ediciones Cátedra.
Meyerowitz, J. (2004). How
Sex Changed: a History of Transsexuality in the United States. Cambridge:
Harvard University Press.
Oudshoorn, N. (2000). The
Birth of Sex Hormones. In L. Schieninger (Ed.), Feminism & The Body (pp. 87-117). New York: Oxford University Press.
Preciado, B.
(2010). Pornotopía. Arquitectura y
sexualidad en “Playboy” durante la Guerra Fría. Barcelona: EDITORIAL
ANAGRAMA.
Pons, A. and Garosi, E. (2016). Trans. In E. Alcántara and H. Moreno Conceptos clave en los estudios de género. México:
PUEG UNAM.
Rubin, G.
(1986). El tráfico de mujeres: notas sobre la “economía política” del sexo. Nueva Antropología. 8(30) 95-145.
Saraswast, A., Weinand, J.D. and
Safer, J.D. (2015). Evidence Supporting the Biologic Nature of
Gender Identity. Endocrine Practice, 21(2) 199-204.
Stone, A. (2007). An Introduction to Feminist Philosophy.
Cambridge: Polity Press.
Vázquez-García, F.
(2018). La invención del sujeto transexual. In M. Bianciotti, M. González and D.
Fernández (Eds.), En todos los colores.
Cartografías del Género y las sexualidades en América Latina. (pp.
13-34) Barranquilla: Ediciones
Universidad Simón Bolívar.
[1]
Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México, México. E-mail: leahmunoz16@gmail.com
[2] The term cisheterosexuality is
composed of the prefix cis- and the
word heterosexuality. The cis- (as
opposed to trans-) comes from
cisgender, a term coined by Trans Studies to designate the condition of an individual
who identifies with the gender that matches the sex he or she was given at
birth. Cisheterosexuality does not simply refer to a specific sexuality, that
of the heterosexual, but rather to a particular condition of gender identity.
[3] Oudshoorn (2000) points out
that the discovery made by endocrinology that sexual hormones were chemical
agents of sexual development, began to build explicative bridges between
different disciplines of biology dedicated to the study of sex that were
previously thought to be in opposition, such as the genetics of sex and the
physiology of sex, and now there began to be a conceptualization of sex as a
complex feedback system. Some years later Money would present a stratified
model of sex, crystallizing research into the biology of sexual development up
until the nineteen fifties.